ORDER/SUBSCRIBE          SPONSORS          CONTACT          WHAT'S NEW          INDEX/SEARCH

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

Reviewer biography

Current Reviews

Review Articles

Book Reviews Archive

Beyond the Limits of Thought

by Graham Priest
Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2003
336 pp., Trade: $74.00
ISBN 0-19-925405-2.

Reviewed by Robert Pepperell

Imagine that a foundational principle of western science, logic, and reason—perhaps the foundational principle—turns out in certain circumstances to be deeply inadequate, even fatally flawed. This is, in effect, what logician Graham Priest sets out to prove in Beyond the Limits of Thought. The foundational principle at stake is that of ‘non-contradiction,’ the axiom of rational belief that asserts that a given state cannot be both true and false at the same time. Since it was proposed and defended by Aristotle in the Metaphysics, the principle of non-contradiction (PNC) has exerted a mighty grip on western thought, serving to underpin much, if not all, reasoned inquiry. But as Priest makes clear, despite the apparent obviousness of the principle, it has periodically been tested during the course of philosophical history and, when pressed, found seriously wanting.

In this mind-bending (and for the uninitiated, sometimes mind-boggling) book, Graham Priest sets out to show that despite the best efforts of some of the most potent minds in history there are states of ‘true contradiction’. The claim is that when we examine the extreme limits of what it is to say, count, know and think, we unavoidably encounter conditions that are both true and not true at the same time; what Priest calls ‘dialethic’ states:

"I claim that reality is, in a certain sense, contradictory… What I mean is that there are certain contradictory statements (propositions, sentences — take your pick) about limits that are true" (p. 295).

As Priest would have it, there are four types of limit to thought, and we are introduced to each in part 1 of the book. The general arguments about the limits of expression, iteration, cognition, and conception, although not overly complex, are too involved to reiterate here. But, in broad terms, they amount to the same thing in each case: That the unknowable is precisely that which we can know nothing about, and that in knowing we can know nothing about it, we know something about it, which is a contradiction, not to say a paradox. On the face of it, this contradiction may seem no more than a vicious piece of philosophical wordplay, until one learns that the combined efforts of Aristotle, Berkeley, Kant, Frege, Russell, Wittgenstein, Heidegger, and Derrida (to name a few) have failed to dispose of this simple, yet unfathomable, conundrum as it appears in its various forms.

"The relationship between the limits of thought and contradiction might be described as a vein that runs prominently through the history of Western philosophy—except that it is more like a major artery" (p. 6).

By examining some of the key arguments in western logic concerning the ultimate nature and limits of mind, Priest sequentially disposes of many significant prior attempts to undo the paradoxes that arise. The only conclusion one can draw, according to Priest, is that the nature and limits of mind are actually paradoxical and that rather than deny this, we should accept it. This solution, of course, will displease, or even threaten, those for whom the PNC is the bedrock of rationality, amongst whom one supposes we can count most scientists and philosophers (as Priest is well aware (p. 4)). It could well be argued that if paradoxes are allowed to prevail unchallenged, we may run the risk of undermining the rationalist project altogether.

In one way, Priest does not go this far; his dialethic strategy is, in fact, a special branch of logic that accepts the existence of true contradictions. But in accepting their existence, dialethic logic does not discard classical logics. Dialethic logic is applicable in those cases where classical logic will not do, in particular, when considering various metaphysical questions concerning the nature and limits of thought, being, and existence, which are, of course, the topics discussed in this case. In another way, however, Priest takes the spirit of his argument to its logical conclusion, stating that: "In particular, it may . . . be rational to accept that dialetheism is both true and false. In a sense, this is what I do accept" (p. 275 n).

Common to many of the paradoxical situations presented here is the problem of self-reference, a notorious source of ambiguity, indeterminacy, and confusion since from at least the time of the Greeks. As Priest frequently and assuredly demonstrates, many of those thinkers who have tried to ‘stand outside’ thought in order to objectively analyse it find themselves hooked on their own horns when their ideas are turned upon themselves. To take as an example Priest’s discussion of Derrida’s deconstructionist project, in which, according to Derrida, a text has no intrinsic, determinate meaning."

". . . but may be taken to mean many things. Now apply this observation to Derrida’s own text. We take Derrida to be advocating a certain view, namely, arguing against presence, the determinacy of sense. Yet, if he is right he is not advocating anything with stable and determinate sense at all. What then are we supposed to make of what he says if there is nothing as such that he says? Or to put it another way, given that he does express certain views, . . . he is expressing something . . . that, if he is right, cannot be expressed" (p. 219).

Despite the fact that there are technical sections of the book that are difficult follow (those not adept at the formal grammar of logical argument will struggle) it is an exhilarating ride, the main destination of which is very clear. Paradoxes are not logical aberrations, nor the result of fundamental errors of conception; they are a part of the fabric of reality as we experience it. The frontispiece contains a seventeenth-century woodcut depicting a traveller reaching through the membrane that encloses our cosmos into the strange domain on the other side. Whenever we reach for the extremity of thought, we implicitly acknowledge what lies beyond it.

Yet however logically this concept is expressed, it seems to me there is a central aspect of experience that is, arguably, overlooked in all the intriguing manoeuvres on the part of the philosophers discussed, and it is this: we either live in a world that is full of intrinsic boundaries (separations, distinctions, objects, etc.) or a world that is totally devoid of them, i.e., one that is utterly continuous in which there are no intrinsic boundaries between things other than those imposed upon the world by human conception. Philosophers might (and do) argue about which is the truer case. If we actually live in a world that is both devoid of intrinsic distinctions and full of conceptually imposed distinctions, we generate a contradiction each time we impose a boundary distinction that, in fact, is not there. Each boundary, therefore, gives rise to a paradox if only because, as Leonardo recognised, all boundaries both separate and connect, but also because the boundary can be shown both to be and not be there.

This remarkable and important book is a thoroughly updated edition of what was originally published in 1995. As the views expressed are contentious to many, Priest includes a section that addresses some of the criticisms his earlier edition provoked. His work is gradually gaining converts, and he remarks that the dialethic view "is now more poplar than it was in 1995," but wryly adds, "it takes the fingers of two hands to count the number of people who subscribe to it" (p. 271). Although not being qualified to judge its merits in the context of contemporary logic, I certainly believe the ideas presented in Beyond the Limits of Thought have an importance that resonates far beyond its technical field.

 

 




Updated 1st December 2004


Contact LDR: ldr@leonardo.org

Contact Leonardo: isast@leonardo.info


copyright © 2004 ISAST